Kant, Immanuel Introduction to Logic ISBN 13: 9780806529745

Introduction to Logic - Softcover

9780806529745: Introduction to Logic
View all copies of this ISBN edition:
 
 
Written during the height of the Enlightenment, Kant’s Introduction to Logic is an essential primer for anyone interested in the study of Kantian views on logic, aesthetics, and moral reasoning. More accessible than his other books, Introduction to Logic lays the foundation for his writings with a clear discussion of each of his philosophical pursuits. For more advanced Kantian scholars, this book can bring to light some of the enduring issues in Kant’s repertoire, and for the beginner, it can open up the philosophical ideas of one of most influential thinkers on modern philosophy. This edition comprises two parts, including the first Introduction to Logic and the second an essay titled The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures, in which Kant analyzes Aristotelian logic. Immanuel Kant was a Prussian philosopher, physicist, and mathematician whose contributions to the study of logic, epistemology, metaphysics, aesthetics, and moral reasoning have had a lasting influence on philosophical scholarship. Born in Königsberg, East Prussia in 1724 to a modest family, Kant was raised Pietist, and initially went to the University of Königsberg to study theology. He later abandoned theology for mathematics and physics after becoming interested in the work of Sir Isaac Newton. He was appointed chair of logic and metaphysics at the University of Königsberg and, at the height of the Enlightenment, began publishing his most famous philosophical texts, including his most important work, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals. Kant has had a tremendous impact on modern philosophy, influencing scholars throughout history, including Karl Marx and G. W. F. Hegel, and he continues to be read and studied today.

"synopsis" may belong to another edition of this title.

About the Author:

Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) has been caricatured as a stiff German professor, whose Stoic habits were so predictable that the people of Königsberg, his hometown, could set their clocks by his daily walks. Kant's life is best described as a heroic struggle to discover order within chaos or, better, an effort to fix human thought and behavior within it proper limits. He lived and worked during the Enlightenment, a time when political, religious, and intellectual freedom erupted across the Western world.

Excerpt. © Reprinted by permission. All rights reserved.:

INTRODUCTION

While Immanuel Kant is certainly one of the most original and influential thinkers of the modern period, he is also among the most opaque. This opacity is grounded, in part, in the profundity of his philosophical ideas and, in part, in his less-than-clear presentation. What makes Kant’s Introduction to Logic truly unique in the context of his other works is both the breadth of the subject matter and the clarity of the discussions. This little book might just as well have been entitled An Introduction to Kant’s Thought, for in it he deals with all of the major issues that had concerned him in his more popular works. Yet his presentation here is far less technical and convoluted and thus far more accessible. For the novice it can serve as an excellent introduction to Kant’s entire philosophy, a philosophy that is generally overwhelming when approached from any of his other books. To the student and scholar of Kant’s thought, the Logic can shed new and interesting light on some enduring problems and issues.

 

Immanuel Kant was born in Königsberg, East Prussia (now Kaliningrad, Russia), on April 22, 1724, the fourth of nine children. His father, Johann Georg, a harness maker, provided the family a modest material existence while his mother, Anna Regina Reuter, seems to have been the source of the family’s spiritual sustenance through her commitment to Pietism, i.e., a form of Protestantism that emphasized the inner workings of faith and personal commitment over organized religion and doctrine. She was a devotee and acquaintance of F. A. Schultz (1692–1763), a professor at the University of Halle and the chief representative of the Pietist movement. Schultz was also the director of the Collegium Fridericianum, a quality high school modeled on the University of Halle. Thus, perhaps owing to his mother’s connections and persuasions, young Immanuel was admitted to this prestigious institution in 1732, at the age of eight.

 

In 1740 Kant entered the University of Königsberg as a theological student, but he soon became enamored of mathematics and physics, especially the work of Sir Isaac Newton. To support himself he served as a private tutor from 1746 to 1755. For the next fifteen years he held the position of Privatdocent (lecturer), during which time his popularity as a teacher increased and his research interests expanded. Although Kant had been raised a Pietist, he, like most writers of the mid-eighteenth century, had been educated and indoctrinated in the philosophy of G. W. Leibniz (1646–1716) and that of his student and expositor, Christian Wolff (1679–1754). During the 1760s, however, he became increasingly critical of the “dogmatism” that characterized the Leibniz-Wolffian approach then prevalent in German universities.

 

In 1770 Kant was appointed to the chair of logic and metaphysics at the University of Königsberg, and so began the most productive period of his career. His chief works of this period were the Kritik der reinen Vernunft (Critique of Pure Reason, 1781), a treatise that revolutionized metaphysics; Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten (Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, 1785), one the most important contributions to moral philosophy ever written; the Kritik der praktischen Vernunft (Critique of Practical Reason, 1788), another important source of his ethical views; and the Kritik der Urtheilskraft (Critique of Judgment, 1790), a book on teleological and aesthetic judgments. Kant died on February 12, 1804. According to the accounts of those present at his deathbed, his last words were, “Es ist gut”—“It is good.”

 

The present book comprises two of Kant’s works. The first is the Introduction to Logic. The second is a short essay published in 1762, entitled, Die falsche Spitzfindigkeit der vier syllogistischen Figuren erwiesen (The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures), in which Kant takes on the long and revered tradition of Aristotelian logic.

 

Kant’s Introduction to Logic might well be described as the best book in his corpus that he didn’t write, and the most readable book that most Kant students almost never read. That Kant didn’t write the book per se is not to deny him either authorship or ownership of the ideas contained therein. From 1755 through 1796, Kant taught logic at least once a year using Georg Friedrich Meier’s textbook, Auszug aus der Vernunftlehre (Extract from the Theory of Reason, Halle, 1752). Kant presented his textbook to his friend and student, Gottlob Benjamin Jäsche, along with its marginalia and loose-leaf notes, to forge into the present work, which was published in 1800. That the book goes largely unread by students of Kant’s philosophy is truly unfortunate. For it is in fact a treasure trove of ideas and information presented in a much less formal fashion than that of his published works.

 

The stylistic simplicity of Kant’s Logic has led many scholars to treat the essay with some skepticism with respect to authorship. However, since the work was put together from the “lecture notes” on Kant’s logic course, it really shouldn’t come as any surprise that it lacks the tedious argumentation and tortuous syntax that typify some of his published works, and that it reflects the straightforward presentation and accessible technique that were said to be characteristics of his lectures. He did, after all, have more than forty years of teaching the material to hone and polish his presentation.

 

Among the many topics dealt with in this cornucopia of ideas, there are six areas of discussion that are of particular interest. These are: (1) logic; (2) metaphysics and epistemology; (3) (the nature and history of) philosophy; (4) aesthetics; (5) moral reasoning; and what we might call (6) commonsense advice.

 

(1) Logic. Since his essay of 1762, Kant had entertained some peculiar ideas with regard to logic, which were ultimately developed and expressed in the “doctrine of elements” presentation in the Critique of Pure Reason (and, in fact, in each of the other two Critiques). Since the present volume was largely composed during the development of Kant’s Critical philosophy, it is not surprising to find it reflecting those positions. Logic is understood to be “a canon of the understanding and of reason . . . [containing] nothing but a priori laws, which are necessary, and apply to the understanding universally” (p. 3). He then goes on to distinguish various misapplications of logic: e.g., dialectical (or “sophistical”), popular and scientific, applied, commonsense and speculative uses, which in each case add contents and thus, distort and destroy its purely formal character. The primary role of logic is “to teach the correct use of reason, that is, the use which is consistent with itself.” Its purpose is to show us how the understanding “ought to proceed in thinking” (p. 4.).

 

(2) Metaphysic and Epistemology. Besides general logic, Kant’s Logic also provides some interesting insights into his metaphysical and epistemic doctrines. “Transcendental Logic,” he tells us, is that “in which the object itself is conceived as an object of the understanding alone; whereas general Logic applies to all objects universally” (p. 5). In other words, general logic expresses the necessary laws in terms of which any rational being whatsoever must rationally function. Transcendental logic, on the other hand, expresses the necessary laws in terms of which human beings must experience and rationally function within the world. Section V (pp. 24–30) contains the most straightforward account of the origin of our (human) cognition to be found anywhere in Kant’s writings. What it lacks in depth it makes up for in clarity. Finally in this context is Kant’s interesting account of the seven degrees of knowledge we have of things (pp. 55–56), which moves from the lowest stage, of merely having “an idea of a thing,” to the highest stage, whereby we “comprehend a thing, that is, to cognize it by the reason, or a priori, in such a degree as is adequate to our purpose” (p. 55).   

 

(3) Philosophy. For Kant, philosophy is both a rational knowledge and a skill. Yet, a philosopher is much more than a conceptual technician. To become a philosopher one must “exercise himself in making a free use of his reason, not a mere imitative and, so to speak, mechanical use” (p. 13). To improve one’s rational skills through, for example, the study of logic, is the scholastic conception of philosophy. To consider the so-called higher questions, such as the purpose of human existence, the nature of reality, etc., is the cosmic conception of philosophy, the one that gives the discipline its dignity. It is only through the unity of these two conceptions that true wisdom is to be obtained. To the question, “Can philosophy be learned?” Kant, interestingly, gives an emphatic no. The reason it cannot be learned is that “it does not exist” (p.16). The history of philosophy is simply “the history of the use of reason,” and the doctrines and views contained therein are nothing more than “objects for the exercise of [one’s] philosophical ability” (Ibid.). The true philosopher (i.e., “one who knows and teaches Wisdom”) must, “as an independent thinker, make a free and independent, not a slavishly imitative, use of his reason” (Ibid.). This discussion does much to dispel the caricature of Kant as a dry, withered-up old formalist (an image created in the nineteenth century by the poet Heinrich Heine).

 

(4) Aesthetics. In Section I, Kant distinguishes sharply between logic, as a set of a priori rules of the understanding and reason, and aesthetics, which he here describes as “the rules of the agreement of knowledge with the laws of the sensibility” (p. 5). Aesthetics is described as “criticism,” or a set of a posteriori rules culled from experience, which may serve to guide us in our evaluation of artistic beauty. Yet, as in the Critique of Judgment, Kant acknowledges the possibility of something he calls an “aesthetically perfect” cognition, i.e., Beauty (p. 27). Here, as in the third Critique, he suggests that while we may disagree about what is beautiful, we must agree that everyone, everywhere acknowledges that something is beautiful.

 

(5) Moral Reasoning. In considering the “horizons” of our knowledge, Kant suggests, as he had in the Critique of Practical Reason, that there is a practical determination with respect to the human will which “is of the greatest importance” (p. 31). The contrast here between “logical” (or “theoretical”) and “practical” reason is developed later on in Section IX, in his distinction between “knowledge” and “belief,”  respectively. Knowledge is “assent from a reason which is both subjectively and objectively adequate” (p. 61). It can be derived either through reason (a priori knowledge) or through experience (a posteriori knowledge). Belief, however, is something very different. It is intimately related to action, to the will. The postulates of Kant’s moral system—freedom, God, and an immortal soul—cannot be known through theoretical reason. Yet, morality, he insists, requires them. And practical reason provides them, via rational belief: “Rational belief, then, can never reach to theoretical knowledge. . . . .[I]t is only a supposition of the reason in a subjective but absolutely necessary practical point of view” (p. 60).

 

(6) Commonsense Advice. This discussion involves the kinds of insights that one might have gotten while having coffee with Kant. The issues addressed here merely scratch the surface of this remarkable little book. What use is pure science? He tells us that, “[e]very logically perfect cognition has always some possible use which, although as yet unknown to us, may perhaps be discovered by posterity” (p.32). What is the value of speculative knowledge? To this he responds that knowledge has its own intrinsic value: “Our understanding . . . is so constituted that it finds satisfaction in mere insight, and even more than in the resulting utility. . . . Man feels in this his own excellence. . . . Men who do not feel this must envy the beasts” (p. 33). How should one’s knowledge, one’s education, generally proceed? Kant provides eight rules for enlarging and improving one’s knowledge (pp. 33–34), and goes on to delineate various errors of learning (pedantry, dilettantism, etc.). This discussion culminates in his instructions on how to be          “truly popular” (hint—“read the ancients”) (p. 38). How can we avoid errors in judgments? He offers three rules to help us avoid errors: think for ourselves; be able to think from the perspectives of others; and think consistently. Just as important, rely on common sense. “Common sense . . . is also in itself a touchstone for detecting the errors of the technical use of the understanding” (p. 48). What kind of erroneous judgment presents the greatest danger to our knowledge? Judging by the extent of the discussion, Kant’s answer would appear to be prejudice (cf. pp. 65–71). “Every prejudice is to be viewed as a principle of erroneous judgment, and from prejudices arise not prejudices, but erroneous judgments” (p. 66). He contends that prejudice arises through imitation (we accept as true what is commonly regarded as true), custom (we accept as true a belief that has been accepted for a long time) and inclination (it is easier to believe what others believe than to believe otherwise). Kant’s discussion here is as fresh and enlightening as it was when it was written.

 

The second piece contained in the present volume is Kant’s early and very technical essay, The False Subtlety of the Four Syllogistic Figures, published in 1762. Here Kant strikes out against the well-entrenched system of Aristotelian logic. To appreciate his criticisms we must first understand something about the system itself.    

 

According to this system, a basic argument can be translated into a categorical syllogism; that is, an argument consisting of two premises and a conclusion. The premises are statements that are assumed to be true, whereas the conclusion is a statement that is inferred from these premises. Consider, for example, the following argument:

 

"About this title" may belong to another edition of this title.

  • PublisherPhilosophical Library
  • Publication date1963
  • ISBN 10 0806529741
  • ISBN 13 9780806529745
  • BindingPaperback
  • Number of pages108
  • Rating

Other Popular Editions of the Same Title

9781112916793: Introduction To Logic

Featured Edition

ISBN 10:  1112916792 ISBN 13:  9781112916793
Publisher: Philosophical Library, 1963
Hardcover

Top Search Results from the AbeBooks Marketplace

Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: 1
Seller:
Books Unplugged
(Amherst, NY, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. Buy with confidence! Book is in new, never-used condition 0.35. Seller Inventory # bk0806529741xvz189zvxnew

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 11.46
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: 1
Seller:
Book Deals
(Tucson, AZ, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. New! This book is in the same immaculate condition as when it was published 0.35. Seller Inventory # 353-0806529741-new

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 11.46
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Seller Image

Kant, Immanuel (CON); Abbott, Thomas Kingsmill (TRN); Coleridge (CON)
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: 5
Seller:
GreatBookPrices
(Columbia, MD, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. Seller Inventory # 6649412-n

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 8.85
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: US$ 2.64
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Seller Image

Kant, Immanuel
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Paperback or Softback Quantity: 5
Seller:
BargainBookStores
(Grand Rapids, MI, U.S.A.)

Book Description Paperback or Softback. Condition: New. Introduction to Logic 0.32. Book. Seller Inventory # BBS-9780806529745

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 11.58
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: > 20
Seller:
Lakeside Books
(Benton Harbor, MI, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. Brand New! Not Overstocks or Low Quality Book Club Editions! Direct From the Publisher! We're not a giant, faceless warehouse organization! We're a small town bookstore that loves books and loves it's customers! Buy from Lakeside Books!. Seller Inventory # OTF-S-9780806529745

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 7.68
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: US$ 3.99
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Seller Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Soft Cover Quantity: 5
Print on Demand
Seller:
booksXpress
(Bayonne, NJ, U.S.A.)

Book Description Soft Cover. Condition: new. This item is printed on demand. Seller Inventory # 9780806529745

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 12.20
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (2024)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Paperback Quantity: 20
Print on Demand
Seller:
Save With Sam
(North Miami, FL, U.S.A.)

Book Description Paperback. Condition: New. Brand New! This item is printed on demand. Seller Inventory # 0806529741

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 12.58
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: > 20
Seller:
Lucky's Textbooks
(Dallas, TX, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. Seller Inventory # ABLIING23Feb2416190211581

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 10.30
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: US$ 3.99
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Kant, Immanuel
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New Softcover Quantity: > 20
Seller:
California Books
(Miami, FL, U.S.A.)

Book Description Condition: New. Seller Inventory # I-9780806529745

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 15.00
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds
Stock Image

Immanuel Kant
Published by Philosophical Library (1963)
ISBN 10: 0806529741 ISBN 13: 9780806529745
New PAP Quantity: > 20
Print on Demand
Seller:
PBShop.store US
(Wood Dale, IL, U.S.A.)

Book Description PAP. Condition: New. New Book. Shipped from UK. THIS BOOK IS PRINTED ON DEMAND. Established seller since 2000. Seller Inventory # L0-9780806529745

More information about this seller | Contact seller

Buy New
US$ 15.69
Convert currency

Add to Basket

Shipping: FREE
Within U.S.A.
Destination, rates & speeds

There are more copies of this book

View all search results for this book